Leont'ev's Genuinely Religious Politics
Modern European consciousness has been
characterized by the way it opposes spiritual independence to the powerful
state. When classifying Schopenhauer as ‘a total solitary’, Nietzsche wrote of
how ‘wherever there has been tyranny, there the solitary philosopher has been
hated; for philosophy offers an asylum to a man into which no tyranny can force
its way, the inward cave, the labyrinth of the heart’.[i]
Within a Soviet context, Orlando Figes has noted, the satire of the ‘omnipresent
bureaucratic state’ in the Strugatskie brothers’ fiction Predatory Things of the Century (1965) centred precisely on how the
people have become ‘spiritually dead’, because under technology’s rule ‘there
is no longer any need for work or independent thought’.[ii]
Thomas Mann’s The Magic Mountain (1924)
foregrounds the argument – advanced in that novel by the character Naphta –
that Enlightenment secularization resulted in the grounding of ‘“all human
conflict”’ in ‘“the clash between the interests of the individual and of
society”’; Settembrini resists this as an ‘“insinuation that the modern state
dooms the individual to the hell of slavery”’.[iii]
The thinking of the Russian conservative
romantic Konstantin Leont’ev (1831-91) was distinctive in that it paired
spiritual independence with an unfree society positively. ‘Parliamentarism is powerless to elevate by itself a
nation that has become spiritually impoverished, whereas the historical periods
that were full of life and creativity were great even without free
institutions.’ Leont’ev argued that in fact political unfreedom could be a
boon. He thought that (as Stephen Lukashevich has put it) ‘the true freedom of
the individual, which was the freedom to express creatively one’s own
personality, was more current in times and places where political freedom was
unknown’.[iv]
The state’s power was held by Leont’ev to be enabled by the fusion of its
unfreedom with personal freedom – a freedom which is seen to be possible even within
a coercive society.
‘The state does not maintain itself by
freedom alone or by restrictions and severity, but by the yet hard-to-grasp
harmony between, on the one hand, the discipline of faith, authority, laws,
traditions and customs, and, on the other hand, the real freedom of the individual, which is possible even in China,
where torture exists.’[v]
The first aspect of Leont’ev’s alignment
of spiritual independence with an unfree society which I want to draw out here,
relates to his views on authority and law. It is helpful to view Leont’ev as representative
of the sort of Russian philosophical tradition to which Lesley Chamberlain was
referring when she wrote that ‘the tradition exists, of a culture which above
all things wishes to be moral by preserving the integrity of the world and the
integrity of others – not their right to be fully fledged individuals so much
as their right to be private souls’.[vi]
Some people fail to fledge, or lack the options to become fully fledged.
Particularly for a member of an excluded or economically inactive social grouping
therefore, cultivation of a spiritual life can become of greater importance than
democratic, right-bearing activity or the entitled pursuit of a career; this is
all the more the case in a society where democracy is illusory or career options
plainly unrewarding. The contrast that Chamberlain poses between ‘fully fledged
individuals’ and ‘private souls’, is thus another formulation of Leont’ev’s
distinction between ‘the individual’s legal
freedom and the personality’s real development
– one that can occur even in a state of slavery’. Nikolai Berdiaev identified
Leont’ev himself as ‘an example of a “personality”, of “an individuality’s
living development”, as distinct from a mere individual, content with an
abstract “freedom of his person”’.[vii]
Leont’ev’s suspicion of abstract legal
freedom articulates what Berdiaev called Leont’ev’s thought’s ‘very Russian
motif’ of exposing ‘the wrongness of external law’ – a motif Berdiaev also
notes in Dostoevskii’s The Brothers
Karamazov (1880).[viii]
The wariness of legal emancipatory claims reappeared in Leont’ev’s remark that
‘the divine truth of the Gospel held out
no promise of earthly happiness, preached no legal freedom, but only an
ethical, spiritual freedom attainable in conditions of the worst slavery’.[ix]
Berdiaev glosses Leont’ev’s attitude here in his comment that ‘In his mind a
state of Christian slavery was more desirable than state Christian freedom’.[x]
Leont’ev’s clear advocacy of spiritual freedom over legal or state freedom,
makes Berdiaev’s assessment that ‘as distinct from the Slavophils he [Leont’ev]
entirely disbelieved in the freedom of the spirit’ difficult to understand – as
indeed does Berdiaev’s judgement that Leont’ev ‘had an extraordinary freedom of
mind, greater perhaps than that of most Russian intellects’.[xi]
Leont’ev contended that ‘our [Russian]
people loves and understands authority better than laws. […] A constitution,
which would undermine Russian authority, would not have time to teach the
people a devotion such as the English
have for their legislature.’ For Leont’ev it was instead Byzantinism which
was - in Lukashevich’s words - ‘the inner Idea of the Russian state which gave
the state its form and its inner balance’. Lukashevich quotes Leont’ev defining
Byzantinism: ‘We know, for instance, that Byzantinism in a state means
autocracy. In religion, it means a Christianity with distinctive traits, which
make it different from the Western Churches’.[xii] The
connection between the Russian evolution of religiosity and coercive government
was made by Leont’ev in a passage cited by Berdiaev.
‘For the Russian people to become truly
a “godly” one, it is necessary for it to be confined,
held down, paternally and conscientiously constrained. It must not be
deprived of its external limitations and
curbs, which have for so long affirmed and inculcated humility and obedience in
it. These qualities constituted its psychic character, and have made of it a
truly great and exemplary people.’[xiii]
For Leont’ev what he elsewhere calls the
‘lawful and sacred right of coercion over our will’, really stands in a
dialectical relation to a (supposedly) weak or submissive character: despotism
affirms weakness, but is also rendered necessary by it. ‘Out of affection for
Russia, I often think that all our mean personal defects are very useful from
the cultural standpoint, for they create
the necessity of despotism, of inequality and of forceful spiritual and
physical discipline.’[xiv]
Leont’ev’s theory of the dynamics of evolution
rested on a notion of coercive cohesion. ‘The highest level of evolution, not
only of the organic matter, but in general, of all the organic phenomena, is
the highest degree of complexity held together by a certain inner and despotic
cohesiveness.’ As Lukashevich notes, with his complexifying stratification of
society Peter the Great ‘created in Russia the conditions that Leontev deemed
ideal for the vitality of the state, namely a maximum of inner diversity knit
together by the despotism of the state form and a leading social force – the
gentry’. Evolution driven by what Lukashevich calls ‘an intransigent organic
law (the “Idea” of the organism)’, had for Leont’ev an innately aesthetic
quality – Lukashevich pointed to Leont’ev’s concept of ‘the “Form” which
reflected the vigour, the personality, the beauty and the “Idea” of the
organism’. That is, for Leont’ev the vitality indebted to discipline was
intrinsically aesthetic. As Lukashevich writes, it is not just that Leont’ev’s
evolutionary theory is applicable to ‘art, philosophy and historical change’;
for Leont’ev, awareness of the dynamics of evolution ‘would permit men to
improve their personal, social and historical life by inducing them to
cultivate esthetics’.
‘[…] Leontev indicated that in nature
equality, freedom and loss of form […] were the destroyers of life, which
demanded inequality, discipline and a unique self-expression. By the same token
“freedom,” equality and loss of form were negating the sense of beauty or
esthetics, which was the outward expression of vitality’.[xv]
Leont’ev’s privileging of coercive
cohesion explains why he was not a populist or nationalist thinker. Berdiaev
saw how according to Leont’ev ‘a great nation survived and prospered by virtue
of the coercive idea dominating its foundation, rather than by virtue of any
autonomous force’. Leont’ev, Berdiaev noted, found ‘truth and beauty in the
universal and organizing principles of the Church and the State, in objective
ideas, that is, rather than in the popular genius or in the principle of
nationality as an independent value’. But really, as Berdiaev goes on to
explain, Byzantine Orthodoxy and autocracy do not possess equal status in
Leont’ev’s view, insofar as a State remains a national element, and Leont’ev (Chaadaev-like)
exalts the objective or religious idea above the national idea. His politics is
an essentially religious politics.
‘Leontiev did not believe that a State could survive without mystical
foundations.’ Berdiaev quotes in this connection:
‘Personal
morality and even personal valour have in themselves no organizing or
governmental principle. The organizing quality is not the outcome of a personal
virtue or of a subjective feeling of honour, but of external and objective ideas, of which religion is the principal one.’[xvi]
Leont’ev’s foregrounding of universal
principles and objectivities manifested too in his view of spiritual life. ‘The
flowering of culture is brought about by transcendental principles and the
objective value of ideas.’ For universal principles discipline and, as Berdiaev
puts it, Leont’ev’s ‘morality justified slavery, coercion and despotism, in
return for political and national power, flowering culture, originality of
spirit’.[xvii]
Thus the second aspect of Leont’ev’s alignment of spiritual independence with
an unfree society which I want to emphasize, concerns his views on the
development of individuals. In Berdiaev’s words, Leont’ev ‘did not love man’s
individualities for their own sake, but he did respect original and powerful
individualities, - “the exclusive, distinct, powerful and expressive
development of characters”’. ‘Individualism and autonomism’, by contrast, he
thought were ‘hostile to such a development of characters or individualities’;
as Leont’ev put it, ‘Egalitarian individualism has destroyed the individuality
of characters.’[xviii]
Leont’ev’s own individual spiritual
make-up led him to conclude, as Berdiaev has written, that ‘there was no
salvation for him in this world, that the world was too great a temptation for
him, and he turned to salvation in the other world, in monasticism’. For
Berdiaev this attitude of Leont’ev’s means that ‘he could not discover the way
to live his religious experience in the world’. In the same way, Leont’ev’s
political thinking is defined by Berdiaev as being characterized by a
separation of spiritual experience from worldly life. ‘In the sphere of
political thought he was the author of a profound conception in which the
relation of Christianity to society was posed in a complex and dualistic
manner.’[xix]
Leont’ev certainly opposed Christianity – his own Christian pessimism – to an
ameliorist social liberalism built around ideas of democracy and progress.
‘True Christianity is […] the strongest opponent of […] petty bourgeois
individualism which, by freeing all in an equal measure and by subjecting all
to the same norms, wants to transform everybody into equally worthy and equally
happy people.’[xx]
I would argue however, contrary to Berdiaev, that precisely through its
opposition of Christianity to bourgeois individualism, Leont’ev’s thought opens
into a genuinely religious politics – rather than a politics which remains
separated from religious experience.
29.4.19
[i]
Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations,
trans. by R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: CUP, 1997), p. 139.
[ii]
Orlando Figes, Natasha’s Dance: A
Cultural History of Russia (London: Penguin Books, 2003; first publ. 2002),
p. 515.
[iii] Thomas
Mann, The Magic Mountain: A Novel,
trans. by John E. Woods (New York: Everyman’s Library, 2005), p. 473.
[iv]
Stephen Lukashevich, Konstantin Leontev
(1831-1891): A Study in Russian ‘Heroic Vitalism’ (New York: Pageant Press,
1967), p. 123 (quoting Leont’ev).
[v]
Leont’ev quoted in Lukashevich, p. 113.
[vi]
Lesley Chamberlain, Motherland: A
Philosophical History of Russia (New York: Rookery Press, 2007; first publ.
[London(?)]: [n. pub.], 2004), p. 280.
[vii]
Nicolas Berdyaev, Leontiev, trans. by George Reavy (Orono: Academic
International, 1968; first publ. London: [n. pub.], 1940), p. 69 (quoting
Leont’ev).
[viii]
Nikolai Berdyaev, The Russian Idea, trans.
by R. M. French, rev. edn (Hudson: Lindisfarne Press, 1992; first publ. London:
Bles, 1947), p. 169.
[ix]
Leont’ev quoted in Leontiev, p. 78.
[x] Leontiev, pp. 55-56.
[xi] Russian, p. 85; Leontiev, p. 69.
[xii]
Leont’ev quoted in Leontiev, pp.
187-88; Lukashevich, p. 137 (quoting Leont’ev).
[xiii] Leont’ev
quoted in Leontiev, p. 176.
[xiv] Leont’ev
quoted in Leontiev, pp. 92, 178-79.
[xv]
Leont’ev quoted in Lukashevich, p. 87; Lukashevich, pp. 143, 88, 89.
[xvi] Leontiev, pp. 162-63, 162, 180 (quoting
Leont’ev).
[xvii]
Leont’ev quoted in Leontiev, p. 165; Leontiev, p. 93.
[xviii] Leontiev, p. 97 (quoting Leont’ev);
Leont’ev quoted in Lukashevich, p. 123.
[xix] Leontiev, pp. 197, 227, 133.
[xx]
Leont’ev quoted in Lukashevich, p. 114.
Comments
Post a Comment