Failures of Russian Liberal Conservatism
For Richard Pipes, writing in his Russian Conservatism and Its Critics: A Study in Political Culture (2005), the ‘quintessence’ of Russian conservatism is ‘autocracy’; whilst historically ‘liberals or conservative liberals’ were those who wished ‘to limit in one way or another the powers of the sovereign’. Pipes maintains of Russia that conservatism has been ‘throughout her history the fundamental theory of government: consistently upheld by the crown and dominant in public opinion’. But the way in which Russia is ‘committed to authoritarian government’ was shown too by post-1917 Communist rule – described by Pipes as ‘the most extreme form of autocratic rule ever known’ – and continues to be shown by Vladimir Putin’s government under which the Russian people, ‘seemingly ready to embrace democracy, have once again, as in 1917, sought safety in submission to “a strong hand”’.[i] Yet despite Pipes’s argument that ‘the dominant strain in Russian political thought throughout history has been a conservatism that insisted on strong, centralized authority, unrestrained either by law or parliament’ (1), Russian Conservatism and Its Critics – as I want to highlight – presents conservatism in Russia as a political strain that is consistently tempered by (failing) attempts at a more liberal politics.
Pipes’s presentation of a conservatism
characterized by failed liberal moments can be distinguished from Paul
Robinson’s more recent characterization of Russian conservatism in terms of its
adherents’ vision of a limited autocracy. Robinson concluded his 2019 study Russian
Conservatism with the statement that, by Russian conservatives, state power
has ‘always been seen as limited by custom and religion, and in more recent
times by law, as well as being restricted in terms of its competencies, that is
to say those things over which it has authority’.[ii] Robinson’s
stress on the idea of limited autocracy complements the main argument of his
book – that Russian conservatism is marked by ‘a preference for organic
change’. Here Robinson evokes not the spasmodic, inadequate bids for change
noticed by Pipes, but instead a continuous progressive movement: ‘change of a
certain, gradual sort that is in keeping, as much as possible, with national
traditions’. Robinson’s book undeniably shows that Russian conservatives have often
propounded the principle of organic change. But it does seem to me that to say
that Russian conservatives typically identify with ideas of a limited
autocracy, or that Russian conservatism is ‘not a philosophy of the status
quo’, risks presenting actual Russian autocracy – for instance in its
contemporary Putinite form – as something that is more flexible and less
aggressive, less tyrannical, than it actually is.[iii]
Pipes’s identification of a conservatism characterized by failed liberal
moments appears to offer an analysis which is more true to reality and hence
more capable of generating a viable alternative to autocracy.
Here I will look into two forms of
failing Russian liberal conservatism: autocrat-enabled liberalization and the
nineteenth-century ‘conservative liberals’.[iv]
Pipes describes the latter phenomenon as a product of the former. He argues
that ‘at least since the accession of the Romanovs, the crown had been the main
source of liberal initiatives’. Peter the Great launched Russia’s
Westernization; Peter III abolished compulsory state service for nobles;
Catherine the Great ‘made possible the emergence of public opinion and with her
1785 Noble Charter created in Russia private property in land’. For Pipes, it
was ‘awareness of this reality’ which ‘led to the emergence of a singular
school of “conservative liberalism”’. Though he notes that Peter Struve
recorded how ‘the term “liberal conservative” was applied by Prince P. A.
Viazemskii in the 1830s to define the politics of Pushkin’, Pipes focusses on
the work of ‘conservative liberals’ later in the nineteenth-century.
Conservative liberalism, as he summarizes it, ‘gave up on political democracy
in the hope that the foundations of a liberal regime in Russia would be laid by
the autocratic monarch and the expectation that in time they would bring about
a constitutional order’ (157).
But to begin with autocrat-enabled
liberalization. A first notable failure of the liberalization initiated by
autocracy relates to the depoliticization or divorce of society from politics that
has typically accompanied autocracy in Russia. Pipes stresses how, as far back
as in Muscovite Russia, ‘the various social groups had no collective rights to
safeguard and, feeling little in common, could not perform a political role’
(22). Moreover, for most of its history Russia ‘knew only autocratic government
that forbade, under severe penalties, any public interference with politics’
(xv). It is certainly the case that Pipes’s account of the purification or
heightened definition of politics in Russia effected by Peter the Great – which
involved the emergence of political theory, as ‘a doctrine of the state’ –
points toward the phenomenon of a politicization of elite (intellectual) life.
For Peter was the first ruler to impose a view of the state as ‘an institution
in its own right, distinct from the person of the monarch, whom [sic] everyone,
the monarch included, was duty-bound to serve’; in addition, by the succession
crisis of 1730, Western European political thought had infiltrated Russia to
the point where ‘her leading polemicists could freely cite Bodin, Hobbes,
Locke, Grotius, and Pufendorf’ (52). Significantly, however, even this
Westernizing politicization could strengthen Peter as autocrat. Enlisted by
Peter, Feofan Prokopovich ‘preached sermons defending royal absolutism with
reference to Natural Law drawn from Western authorities’ such as the theorists
named above. Prokopovich’s principal treatise followed Christian Wolff in
arguing that ‘since the monarch’s foremost duty was to attend to the well-being
of his subjects, he required unlimited powers’ (Pipes: 55). Pipes finds the
treatise to be ‘the first in Russia to define and vindicate royal absolutism in
theoretical terms with reference to the political contract’ (56).
Despite the phenomenon of Petrine
politicization, the depoliticization which typically accompanies autocracy in
Russia returned – so Pipes argues – as a consequence of the 1730 succession
crisis. Pipes quotes Struve’s comment that the events of 1730 – which concluded
in Anna’s rejection of Dmitrii Golitsyn’s reforming ‘conditions’ to her
accession – ‘had for the political destinies of Russia a fateful, predetermined
quality’, in that they ‘laid down in definitive form the tradition of basing
the Russian monarchy on the political submissiveness of the cultured classes’.
Pipes agrees that the events of 1730 ‘did seal a compact between the crown and
the Russian nobility by virtue of which the latter, in effect, surrendered any
claim to political power: the crown showered the gentry with privileges in
exchange for staying out of politics’. The freeing of nobles from compulsory
state service in 1762 and the 1785 charter giving them their estates in private
ownership, show Pipes how ‘step by step the monarchy bought off the nobility’
(62-63); being limited to the pursuit of these two gains, the influence the
nobility did exert proved that ‘its interests were purely self-serving’. Nonetheless,
a proto-intelligentsia, or what Pipes calls a ‘thin layer of gentry critics of
autocracy’, appeared ‘as early as the middle of the eighteenth century’ (63).
This original intelligentsia was a minority element of the ‘public opinion’
which emerged as a result of the gains granted the nobility in 1762 and 1785,
which had created ‘for the first time, a leisured and propertied class […] able
to view itself as “society” (obshchestvo)’ (64).
This account of eighteenth-century
Russian history supports Pipes’s more general argument that depoliticization in
an autocratic Russia can actually generate a type of potentially positive
political influence, in the form of ‘public opinion – what Russians call obshchestvennoe
mnenie’. Pipes suggests that the fact that throughout Russian history
autocracy has ‘forbade, under severe penalties, any public interference with
politics’, has meant that ‘political concerns and passions found their main
outlet in the realm of ideas’. This has enabled in turn both a love of
intellectual history and ‘a rich development of public opinion […] that even if
unable to influence politics directly did so obliquely by compelling the
monarchy to react to it either by repression or concessions’ (xv).
Pipes thus presents depoliticization and
public opinion as twinned aspects of autocrat-enabled liberalization. He draws
attention to how, by publishing the Nakaz [Instruction] and
convening the Legislative Commission of 1767-69, Catherine herself ‘defined the
principles of good government’ and gave Russia’s upper class ‘an opportunity
publicly to discuss to what extent the country met its criteria’ – this meant
that ‘Russian public opinion emerged in the 1760s owing to this initiative, and
it never died down until silenced by the Communists’ (72). Public
opinion-forming higher education and learning were important features of
Russia’s autocrat-led Westernization process; it was Catherine who allowed for
the first time the establishment of private printing presses (64, 65). Nikolai
Novikov’s large publishing enterprise – publisher of 28% of all the books
published in Russia during the 1780s (67-68) – was allowed to operate. But this
was, Pipes adds, ‘presumably because he never criticized institutions but only
behaviour’ (67). Novikov was a rationalist Freemason intellectual, preoccupied
with issues of morality, and was ‘extremely careful not to write anything that
could be interpreted as criticism of autocracy’ (68). But even he ‘came under
pressure from the court to mute his criticism’ (67), Pipes writes, and his case
came to exemplify how ‘the instant public opinion turned critical of the
government, they resorted to repression’ (64). Novikov’s situation illustrated perfectly
how, in relation to its twin effects of depoliticization and the emergence of
public opinion, autocrat-enabled liberalization in effect represented a
failure. ‘Although a writer who deliberately avoided political subjects,
Novikov made an indirect contribution to Russian political theory by treating
constitutional forms as irrelevant.’ The compatibility of his goals of
‘enlightenment and virtue’ with any regime ‘had the unintended effect of
justifying autocracy’ (68): also effectively reconfirming Catherine’s inadequate
liberalization.
By the final years of the reign of
Nicholas I, as Pipes observes, censorship had grown to ‘grotesque dimensions’ (117)
in Russia. This contributed to the way in which ‘after the thirty-year reign of
Nicholas I [1825-55], there was in Russia nothing resembling public opinion:
there were only isolated salons and circles’. It was the Slavophile publicist
Ivan Aksakov who, in developing the concept of ‘obshchestvo,’ focussed
attention on how – as Pipes puts it – ‘Russia had as yet no obshchestvo but
only narod [the people]’. Aksakov was attempting to reformulate ‘obshchestvo’
to refer not so much to society but instead to public opinion. For Aksakov, ‘it
was through education and public discourse that the narod would transform
itself into obshchestvo’, as Pipes summarizes; ‘freedom of expression was to
him the life-blood of obshchestvo.’ Aksakov himself defined obshchestvo
as ‘a narod that is conscious of itself’, or ‘that environment in which takes
place conscious intellectual activity of a given people, an environment created
by the entire spiritual might of the narod which is developing its national
consciousness’ (134, quoting Aksakov).
The fact that Aksakov thought a free
press more important than representative institutions points towards the
depoliticizing tendency of his elevation – through the concept of obshchestvo
– of popular consciousness or spiritual life. Pipes emphasizes how, because in
Russia ‘the state stood apart from the population’, the term ‘obshchestvo’
always had ‘designated everything that was not government’; Slavophile
thinkers such as Ivan and his brother Konstantin continued to make ‘a
distinction between state and obshchestvo: the state should confine itself to
politics and not interfere with the “land”’. The state, Ivan wrote, should be
restricted to ‘the superficial and remain in those modest limits assigned to it
by the spiritual and moral activity of obshchestvo itself’ (133, quoting
Aksakov). His projected state also required ‘the active support’ (134) of an obshchestvo,
Pipes noted. For Aksakov,
‘In constituting the Russian state, the
Russian people conceded to the former, in the person of the tsar, the full
freedom of governmental action, the unlimited freedom of state power – and as
for itself, eschewing all claims to power, all dominant intervention in the
realm of the state or supreme governmental authority, mentally acknowledged for
the land the full freedom of social and spiritual life, the freedom of opinion,
that is, of thought and speech.’ (quoted on 133)
Claiming for itself and ‘the land’ the
status of public opinion, or social, cognitive and linguistic rights, Aksakov’s
narod would thereby abjure political rights (134), and confirm unlimited
autocracy – ‘the unlimited freedom of state power’ – as its necessary partner. As
Konstantin Aksakov would phrase it in 1855, ‘To the government unlimited
freedom to rule, to which it has the exclusive right; to the people full
freedom of life, both outward and inner, which the government
safeguards.’ We can identify this dialectic of autocratic government and
popular freedom as the bridge between the Slavophile concern with obshchestvo
and the thinking of the ‘conservative liberals’, who would come to control
the centre of Russian politics until the end of the nineteenth-century (159).
Pipes appends to the Konstantin Aksakov quotation the comment that ‘it was a
novel theory that anticipated the ideas of the conservative liberals like
Konstantin Kavelin and Boris Chicherin’ – thinkers who ‘a generation later, would
try to combine autocracy with civil rights’ (110, quoting Aksakov).
Pipes ultimately dismisses conservative
liberalism as ‘an abstract and unrealistic doctrine’, precisely because its projected
combination of coexistence of autocracy and civil rights was ‘plainly quixotic’
on account of the fact that ‘given that every political entity strives to
enhance its authority, it could not help but view civil rights and liberties as
troublesome obstacles and strive to eliminate them’. He underlines that even
the leader of the conservative liberal school, Chicherin, when disillusioned by
the repressive policies of Alexander III and the persecution of Jews, ‘gave up
the ideal of a progressive absolutism’. Chicherin came to feel that the
combination of the unlimited powers of the tsar with the bureaucracy threatened
Russia with catastrophe, and concluded that, as Pipes writes, ‘the only way to
forestall such an outcome was to limit tsarist authority’. In effect, Russian
liberal conservatism had failed once more, as liberalism was forced to detach
itself from adherents to autocracy: ‘the Russian liberal movement became
radicalized, its leadership passing to those elements, concentrated in the
zemstva [rural councils], which demanded and in 1905 won for Russia a
constitutional regime’ (163). But this brief-lived regime would be removed in
February 1917, before in October of that year a new type of autocracy arose,
the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, which was defined by its head, Lenin, as
‘power that is limited by nothing, by no laws, that is restrained by absolutely
no rules, that rests directly on coercion’ (quoted on 173-74).
Breaking the historical – for instance
Ivan Aksakov’s – separation of the Russian people from ‘all claims to power’,
the dictatorship of the proletariat would invest the narod with coercive
force and in so doing convert obshchestvo itself into autocracy. How
different this conception of obshchestvo was from that of a figure whom
Pipes calls ‘the earliest Russian political thinker to appreciate the
importance of public opinion and to insist that a government that failed to
gain its support was inherently weak and unstable’: the state servant Mikhail
Speranskii. Speranskii, who was quite possibly the most vital harbinger of a
viable liberal conservatism, came to prominence during a period thus far
omitted from this mini-narrative of Russian political history: the reign of
Alexander I (1801-25). For Speranskii public opinion was of importance, not as
something to be instrumentalized and elevated into autocracy, coercion or
‘claims to power’, but simply in itself. In his 1802 memorandum ‘About the
Force of Public Opinion’, he maintained that public opinion, in Pipes’s words,
‘being a force independent of laws and governmental institutions’, could
‘either support governments or topple them’. In the introduction to the
constitutional reform project which he went on to draft for Alexander in 1809,
Speranskii clarified how ‘the origin and source of [legislative, executive, and
judiciary] powers reside in the people: because these powers are nothing else
than the moral and physical forces of the people in their relation to the
community’ (83, quoting Speranskii).
Anticipating by some decades, with his
idea of moral ‘forces of the people’, the Slavophile notions of popular
consciousness or spiritual life, Speranskii was also in accord with the
Slavophiles’ traditional Russian separation of the people from all claims to
power, as when he proclaimed – as no-one had before in Russia and, Pipes
thinks, under the influence of the French Revolution – that ‘no government at
odds with the spirit of the times can stand up to its all-powerful action’ (quoted
on 84). Arguably it is this sort of radicalization of the concept of popular
opinion, that makes of it more than an effect of failing, autocrat-enabled
liberalization, that marks the true importance of Speranskii’s work towards
reform. When his 1809 reform plan is described, as it is by James H.
Billington, as ‘the most serious plan for the introduction of representative
and constitutional forms into the Russian monarchy that was to appear for nearly
a century’, this is in effect simply to acknowledge, with Pipes, how
Speranskii’s plans ‘pointed to the necessity of limiting in some way the
arbitrary authority of the Russian ruler, transforming him from a despot into a
genuine monarch (in Montesquieu’s definition of the word)’ (84-85).[v] In
this way Speranskii’s ideas resembled Nikolai Karamzin’s ‘conception of a
monarchy absolute but in a narrow sphere’ (88), or indeed the Slavophiles’
conception of ‘an autocracy that was strictly confined in scope and did not
encroach on the private lives of its citizens’ (110). The idea of limited
autocracy, as we saw, remains the focus of contemporary historian Paul
Robinson. But Speranskii’s radicalization of public opinion and the stress he
laid on the reliance of the political regime on it – ‘the manner of thought of
the present time is utterly contrary to the manner of governance’ – enabled him
to suggest that the ‘all-powerful action’ of popular consciousness could
substantially undermine, rather than just limit, autocracy in Russia. ‘In the
general progress of human reason, our government finds itself presently in the
second era of the feudal system – that is, in the era of autocracy, and,
without a doubt, is moving directly toward freedom.’ (quoted on 84)
17.2.22
[i] Russian
Conservatism and Its Critics: A Study in Political Culture (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2005), pp. xii, xv, xii (further references to Russian
Conservatism and Its Critics are given after quotations in the text).
[ii] Russian
Conservatism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2019), p. 215.
[iii]
Robinson, p. 5.
[iv] Pipes
does not distinguish between liberal conservatism and conservative liberalism.
[v] James
H. Billington, The Icon and the Axe: An Interpretive History of Russian
Culture (New York: Vintage Books, 1970; first publ. [New York(?)]: Knopf,
1966), p. 262.
Comments
Post a Comment