Koselleck, Politics and Discourse
In West German political theory of the mid-1950s, notes Niklas Olsen in his History in the Plural (2012), the public sphere – die Öffentlichkeit – emerged as ‘das akademische Thema der Stunde’: the academic theme of the hour.[i] Probably the two most important resulting West German studies considering the public sphere were Reinhart Koselleck’s Critique and Crisis [Kritik und Krise (1959)], and Jürgen Habermas’s The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere [Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit (1962)]. The relationship between these two texts was already apparent in terms of their reception history: in 1960, before publishing his own book, Habermas produced a double review of Critique and Crisis alongside a dissertation by Hanno Kesting. As Olsen writes, in fact Habermas’s subsequent book offered an interpretation of the Enlightenment project and the status of the modern European public sphere that ‘simultaneously overlapped and conflicted’ with the interpretation in Koselleck’s work. Olsen quotes Peter Uwe Hohendahl: ‘Where Koselleck perceived decline (already during the eighteenth century), Habermas saw the beginning of modernity, containing the very project that was supposed to shape postwar Germany.’ (81)
Olsen draws on useful expository articles
from Jeremy Pompkin and Anthony J. La Vopa in order to summarize how, to the
extent that Habermas’s account of ‘the rise of the public sphere and of the
possibilities of human communication’ was a ‘direct response’ to Koselleck’s
account of these issues, it also ‘fundamentally conflicted’ with Koselleck’s
treatment. In Olsen’s words, Habermas outlines a ‘public sphere of rational
debate’ which is ‘guided by a norm of rational argumentation and critical
discussion in which the strength of one’s argument was more important than
one’s social belonging’. But whilst Habermas’s invocation of a bourgeois world
of ‘coffeehouses, literary salons, and the print media’, and the sort of rootless,
desocialized sociablility that world enabled, meant that he underlined ‘the
possibilities of openness, dialogue, and consensus in processes of
decision-making in the public sphere, Koselleck emphasized the existence of secrecy,
domination, and conflict’. Olsen pinpoints the way in which Habermas valued the
Enlightenment as a discursive Enlightenment:
‘[…] where Habermas optimistically
interpreted the Enlightenment public sphere as an unfulfilled promise of how a
new kind of human communication can break down hierarchical power
relationships, Koselleck pessimistically spoke of the pathogenesis of the
Enlightenment and highlighted the destructive potential of Enlightenment
thought and the public sphere in modern politics.’ (82)
Chris Thornhill has observed how
Habermas’s conception of a discursive Enlightenment and resultant view that –
to state it plainly – politics is discourse – continued to inform his
1970s debates with a slightly younger conservative thinker than Koselleck,
Niklas Luhmann: where Luhmann argued that ‘political legitimacy is
smooth-running administration’, Habermas maintained that ‘legitimate politics
arises from discursive interaction’.[ii] I
want to show now that Koselleck, by contrast, asserts politics against
discourse.
In Critique and Crisis, John
Locke is identified as the first to notice the rise of moral criticism – the
appearance of new moral laws – in the new bourgeois public sphere. This
phenomenon, Koselleck saw, undermined existing criteria for political
decision-making: ‘Which authority decides? The moral authority of the citizen
or the political authority of the state? Or both of them jointly?’ For
Enlightenment philosophers, a subordination of politics to morality, or what
Olsen calls a rejection of ‘the authority of the state on behalf of the
authority of morality’, naturally accorded with their critique of the
absolutist state. Moreover, in Koselleck’s outline, politics began to be
considered as ‘evil’, in that it prevented morality from unfolding. In
consequence citizens, as Olsen explains, sought ‘protection from the state in
the institutions of the public sphere, where the moral criticism had to be
carried out in secrecy – and with the claim of being unpolitical – as it
conflicted with the statutes of the absolutist state’ (49, quoting Koselleck).
Post-1789, for Koselleck, the lack of
resolution of the contradiction between morality and politics still entailed a
failure – as Olsen writes – ‘to transform the Enlightenment
crisis-consciousness into rational and responsible political action, where the
existence of enemies is recognized’. The rise of secular eschatological philosophy
of history such as Hegel’s meant that agents ‘sought refuge in
historical-philosophical ideas of future worlds with reference to which they
sought to carry out their utopian political plans and moreover acquitted
themselves from the responsibility of their actions’. Like his friend Carl
Schmitt, when faced at this time by the Cold War, in Critique and Crisis Koselleck
presented a modern world ‘where the conditions for a durable political order
are absent as long as historical-philosophical worldviews prevent the
recognition of political opponents and of political responsibility’ (52).
Olsen’s account emphasizes Koselleck’s
focus on political life in the Schmittian sense of ‘taking responsibility and
making decisions’ (23). Koselleck sensed, Olsen adds, that ‘the utopian
rejection of political authority instead led to an authority based on ideology,
where supposedly anti-authoritarian Enlightenment concepts such as “reason,”
“equality,” and “morality” were used as weapons of power and control’ (49-50).
This suspicion of utopianism and its concomitant work of depoliticization is
also aligned – as indeed it was by Victor Gourevitch in his ‘Foreword’ to the
English translation of Critique and Crisis – to what has importantly been
described (by Gourevitch) as Koselleck’s wish to ‘restore the
characteristically Hobbesian awareness that there is no escaping the
constraints of political life’, along with Thomas Hobbes’s sense that it is not
possible ‘to reduce some measure of contingency, conflict and compulsion to the
status of differences of opinion or to resolve them by discussion and peaceful
competition’. As Gourevitch stated, Koselleck ‘shares the conviction, so
forcibly articulated by Hobbes, that the only alternative to politics that
takes these constraints into account is the war of all against all’.[iii]
The Cold War is seen to be a product of the substitution of a politics
recognizing real constraints, such as the reality of conflict itself, with
competing ideology-based authorities.
In Gourevitch’s account, Hobbes – and
then Koselleck also – resists the reduction of features of political reality to
elements of discourse (‘differences of opinion’), which would be assimilable within
processes of discursive arbitration (‘discussion and peaceful competition’). It
would seem that, briefly put, and whilst for Habermas politics is discourse,
Koselleck asserts politics against discourse. Certainly, in Critique and
Crisis, when he draws out Pierre Bayle’s exclusion of ‘the sphere of
criticism from the sphere of the State’, Koselleck holds out criticism as one
example of a discursive discipline which represents a depoliticized activity.
‘Within the Republic of Letters the unpolitical quest for truth reigns.’ Koselleck’s
account also lets us see that the separation of politics from discourse which
Hobbes stressed and foregrounded as a defining modern rift was not such an absolute
one prior to Hobbes. Hobbes himself was identified in his own time as a
practitioner of both criticism and politics: Koselleck points out that, on
account of their common opposition to the ‘ecclesiastical authorities’, as
‘critics’ in a dual sense practitioners of rational Biblical criticism and
political commentary ‘often formed a personal union, like [Jean] Bodin and
Hobbes, who were considered outstanding both as Biblical critics and
“politicians”’. Further, Koselleck notes how Aristotle’s use of language
derived (like the words ‘criticism’, ‘crisis’, Kritik, Krise)
‘from the Greek xρίνω: to differentiate, select, judge, decide’, had already allied
the critical, discursive activity of legal judgement to politics, citizenship.
‘When the judge’s decision specifically
is meant, the term αρxή xριτιxή carries the sense of creating order, as
Aristotle used it (Pol. 1253a; 1275a, b; 1326b). […] Only he who
participates in the office of judge (αρxή) is a citizen.’[iv]
Olsen sees how the opposition of a
politics recognizing real constraints to progressivist philosophy of history
and utopianism, which we find in Critique and Crisis, reflects the
influence of Karl Löwith’s 1949 text Meaning in History, of which
Koselleck was co-translator (22). Löwith’s postwar emphasis on historical
contingency is found in statements such as ‘[man’s] planning and guessing, his
designs and decisions, far-reaching as they may be, have only a partial
function in the wasteful economy of history which engulfs them, tosses them,
and swallows them’ (quoted on 23). Koselleck in turn, as Olsen puts it,
‘focussed on the possibility of crisis, conflict, and war, on change and
contingency, and he nurtured a much deeper scepticism [than historian Hans-Ulrich
Wehler] toward every kind of long-term planning, morality, and belief in
societal progress’ (16). Like Hobbes, as we have seen, Koselleck also opposes
politics admitting ‘contingency, conflict and compulsion’ to opinionated discourse
amenable to resolution by ‘peaceful competition’ (Gourevitch). Yet it is
possible to wonder whether Koselleck’s concern with a politics accepting
contingency has relevance beyond the immediate postwar historical context which
generated it. Referring to the original dissertation form of Critique and Crisis,
Olsen observed how ‘while Koselleck did not subject the plot line or the line
of argumentation in the dissertation to major revisions between 1954 and 1959,
the intellectual-political climate in Germany underwent considerable changes in
this period’. (1954 was the year following the dissertation’s submission; 1959
was its publication date). Whereas during what Olsen calls ‘the long period from
around 1900 to the 1950s’, tropes of ‘uncertainty, change, and crisis had
dominated social-political thought’, by the later 1950s ‘a stronger faith in
the capability and durability of political democracy’, alongside socio-economic
improvements, meant that (West) Germans had become ‘increasingly oriented
toward concepts such as stability, welfare, and progress’ (80). Does this shift
of focus of socio-political attitudes away from an understanding of politics in
terms of contingency and conflict begin to undermine the validity of
Koselleck’s thinking around politics and discourse?
The continuing relevance of Koselleck’s opposition
of a politics accepting contingency to conflict-resolving discourse –
Gourevitch’s ‘discussion and peaceful competition’ – seems to me to be most
apparent in terms of the resistance which Koselleck’s upholding of politics
admitting contingency enables to Habermas’s thinking of domination-free
discourse. As Olsen observes, in his 1987 article ‘Historik und Hermeneutik’
[‘History and Hermeneutics’] Koselleck explicitly ‘challenges Habermas’s ideal
of herrschaftsfreier Diskurs, that is, the contention that we can
critically evaluate political life from the perspective of a rational consensus
that is attained in a herrschaftsfrei (domination-free) practical
discourse’ (99 n. 138). You could say that politics can only become discourse
for Habermas because discourse – so he asserts – can achieve the rational
evaluation of political life. This assertion, moreover, is why Habermas’s
theory of discourse – as Thornhill suggests – would be pitched against
Luhmann’s theory of the functional system of the political institution. ‘In
opposition to Luhmann’s functionalism, Habermas puts forward a
non-institutionalist theory of discourse, in which the ethical claims of
domination-free communication cannot be assimilated to systemic rationality.’[v] Yet
Habermas’s vaunting of ethical discourse (or discursive ethics) and the reason
of academic institutions against political-institutional rationality had
already been questioned in the work of the ‘liberal conservatives’ who
clustered around the Münster philosopher Joachim Ritter during the 1950s and
1960s. These thinkers, some of whom – as Olsen writes – ‘knew and cooperated’
(35 n. 36) with Koselleck – sought to reclaim ethics in the face of Habermasian
reason and morality:
‘As Verfassungspatrioten (constitutional
patriots) they have instead attempted to defend and improve the
liberal-democratic pillars of the German Federal Republic by emphasizing
“responsibility against attitude, institutionalized decision against ideas of a
discourse free of domination, tradition and ethics [Sittlichkeit]
against idealized reason and morality.”’ (16, quoting Jens Hacke)
1.5.22
[i]
Niklas Olsen, History in the Plural: An
Introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck (New York: Berghahn, 2014; first publ. 2012), p. 98 n. 126; Olsen
refers us to Stephan Schlak, Wilhelm
Hennis: Szenen einer Ideengeschichte der Bundesrepublik (Mŭnchen: 2008) for details. (Further
references to History in the
Plural are given after quotations
in my text).
[ii] Chris
Thornhill, Political Theory in Modern Germany: An Introduction (Cambridge:
Polity Press, 2000), p. 204.
[iii] ‘Foreword’,
in Reinhart Koselleck, Critique and Crisis: Enlightenment and the
Pathogenesis of Modern Society (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988), pp. vii-x
(p. ix).
[iv]
Koselleck, pp. 112, 106, 103 n. 15.
[v]
Thornhill, p. 203.
Comments
Post a Comment