Walicki's Slavophile Conservative Utopia
‘In
some sense all these dreamers seeking the past – to whom I belonged for the
three days I spent walking Lvov’s streets and parks – are the ideal
conservatives, they replicate perfectly conservatives’ impotence. They search
for something that doesn’t exist, something that may never have existed, […].
They seek better, more beautiful times, and even if some obliging shaman agreed
to resurrect what they desire for five minutes, that is, life before the
disaster, the crowds, the clouds, the window displays, the shrubs before the
disaster, they would still cry out in dismay, “Oh no, that’s not it, it was far
more marvellous before!”’
-Adam Zagajewski, ‘Should We Visit Sacred Places?’
Writing of ‘the anti-capitalist character’ of the Slavophiles’ worldview in his magisterial account The Slavophile Controversy (1975), the great Polish intellectual historian Andrzej Walicki observed that ‘it is precisely this utopian Weltanschauung which is the most original aspect of Slavophilism and ensures it a place in the history of ideas’.[i] As a ‘strongly utopian variety of conservatism’, the classical Slavophilism of the 1840s represented ‘not so much an ideological defence of an existing tradition, as a utopian attempt to rehabilitate and revive a lost tradition’. Even in the more realist Russian social climate of the 1850s, Walicki notes, ‘the more consistent Slavophile “romantics”’ such as Ivan Kireevskii (1806-56) still ‘clung to their uncompromising utopianism’: Kireevskii ‘never gave up his utopian belief that a return to lost traditions was a prerequisite of progress’. Walicki classifies Kireevskii in terms of his ‘conservative and Orthodox Christian romanticism’.[ii]
When summarizing the Slavophiles’ view
of the Russian people’s historical mission, Walicki identified ‘certain
universal ideals’ which usefully describe the utopian ideals of the Slavophile
thinkers: ‘for the Slavophiles this mission had been the defence of the principles
of “true Christianity”, social integrity, and spiritual wholeness’.[iii] In
so far as these utopian ideals reflect what Lesley Chamberlain has called
Russian philosophy’s ‘desperate need for a principle or set of beliefs to hold
the country together as one coherent community or society’, they show the
Slavophile mission to be entirely representative of Russia’s philosophical
mission as summarized by Chamberlain. ‘From the first Schellingians to the last
Communists, philosophy in Russia during its long tradition 1815-1991 aimed at
integration.’[iv]
Walicki’s account enables us to see how the Slavophiles were distinguished by
the accent their conservative utopian thinking lays on spiritual integration. He underlines their concern with ‘the “wholeness”
(tsel’nost’) of spirit’. ‘Their
return to the past – to Orthodoxy and old communal traditions – was part of
their nostalgia for the “wholeness” (tsel’nost’)
of spirit, lost as a result of Europeanization.’[v]
As Walicki writes, Kireevskii theorized
that ‘types of social integration and types of personal integration (or
disintegration) are strictly interdependent’. Personal division or spiritual
fragmentation was ‘one aspect of the dualism pervading all spheres of life in
Europe which was introduced into Russia with the Petrine reforms’. This dualism
in turn stretches back to ‘the dichotomy between Christian and rationalist
principles inherited from classical Roman civilization’.[vi]
Walicki emphasizes that, for Kireevskii, it was not ‘Europe and Russia’ that
were seen as ‘irreconcilable opposites’, but instead ‘rationalism and pure
Christianity’. ‘What he was primarily interested in was something affecting the
internal development of both Russia and Europe – namely the contrast between a
Christian society and a society based on rationalism.’[vii]
In the remainder of this piece I want to continue to explore how Slavophile
ideals of spiritual integration emerged out of this antinomy.
Walicki found that ‘it is clear that the
most widely applicable negative frame of reference for Slavophile doctrine was
“rationalism”’. He went on to define the Slavophiles’ conception of rationalism
in terms of ‘the rationalist interpretation of the personality and of
inter-personal relations, which in the nineteenth century was associated
primarily with the capitalist rationalization of production processes’. He
explains that, having made its first Russian appearance in the work of Vladimir
Odoevskii, ‘the characteristic conservative-romantic attack on capitalism and
its corollary, the romantic critique of rationalism’, was ‘taken up and
developed’ by the Slavophiles. Kireevskii’s philosophical criticism of
rationalism derived from what Walicki calls the ‘German romanticists’; for
example, Kireevskii’s assertion that ‘a bare logical concept cannot grasp
reality as such’ repeated Schelling’s arguments (Kireevskii had attended
Schelling’s lectures in Munich in 1830). In Kireevskii’s article ‘On the
Necessity and Possibility of New Principles in Philosophy’, as Walicki notes, German
philosophy ‘taken in conjunction with’ Schelling’s philosophy of revelation is
seen as the basis of an independent Russian philosophy. Yet the Slavophiles
also understood the creation of a philosophy based on the principles of faith
to involve an initial ‘critical transcending of German philosophy by depriving
it of its dangerous cutting-edge – rationalism’.[viii]
Kireevskii’s critique of rationalism had
an undeniable social dimension, attacking social disintegration: Walicki observes
that the critique ‘was directed not only at bourgeois rationalism – the
rationalism of the calculating merchant and manufacturer – but also at the
bureaucratic rationalism of absolute monarchy’. The way in which ‘rationally
conceived social bonds […] intensify social atomization’, reflects how ‘the
autocratic rule of reason intensifies the disintegration of the psyche’. Yet
despite the social dimension of Kireevskii’s critique of rationalism, it seems
fair to say that the critique primarily aims towards the ideal of personal or
spiritual integration. As Walicki points out, the Slavophiles, after all, ‘were
willing to grant the value of Hegelian reason, but only as an element
subordinate to “integral wholeness”’. That is, for the Slavophiles it was more
important to strive for tsel’nost’
than to attack the merchant’s reason. Kireevskii theorized, Walicki writes,
that Hegelian reason went against ‘“Orthodox thinking”’ ‘only in so far as it
sets itself up as the highest cognitive faculty’.[ix]
As Walicki summarized ‘New Principles in Philosophy’:
‘The ideal personality portrayed in the
essay is an integral structure with a vital core and “inner focus” that serves
to harmonize the separate psychic powers and safeguards the inner unity and
“wholeness” (tselostnost’, tsel’nost’) of the spirit. As natural
reason is only one of these psychic powers, man can only preserve his inner
wholeness by subordinating reason to his “total” psyche.’[x]
Walicki adopts the term ‘integralism’,
so as to distinguish reason from the ‘whole’ personality defined as ‘a total
spiritual structure embracing reason but as a non-autonomous and entirely
submissive faculty’. Recalling the influence on Kireevskii of German romantic
philosophy, Walicki points to Friedrich Schlegel’s Philosophy of Life (1828) as ‘an excellent and typical example of
the anti-rationalistic “integralism” of the conservative romantics’. For
Schlegel in that work, philosophy’s main task was to liberate the soul from the
‘autocratic rule of reason’ and reconstruct man’s ‘primary unity’ with the help
of religious faith. Likewise for the Slavophiles, inner ‘wholeness’ was (in
Walicki’s words) ‘a quality which depends on faith and is threatened by
autonomy’.[xi]
In Kireevskii’s words, the essence of faith was the attempt ‘to concentrate the
separate psychic powers into one single power’. Interestingly, however,
Kireevskii also saw faith as contingent on ‘inner wholeness’, maintaining that
it ‘embraces man’s whole personality and manifests itself only when inner
wholeness has been attained and then in proportion to the degree of this
wholeness’.[xii]
For Kireevskii the inner wholeness of
spiritual people was also, as Walicki puts it, ‘a function of the organic ties
binding them to the community; […] their exceptionally strong faith springs
from their exceptionally close fusion with the Church as a social organism’.
The Slavophiles were ‘more consistent in their criticism of rationalism than
like-minded philosophers in Germany’, precisely because theirs (unlike the
aristocratic thought of Odoevskii or Pëtr Chaadaev) was a ‘social philosophy,
[…] which claimed to have found in Orthodoxy and the communal traditions of the
Russian people the values irrevocably lost in Europe’. The Slavophiles argued
that faith stems from collective religiosity, or from what Walicki calls ‘a
life guided by tradition and participation in a supra-individual community’.[xiii]
Just as the later conservative romantic Konstantin
Leont’ev understood the twinning of the maintenance
of an unfree society with the existence of personal freedom, Kireevskii noted
repeatedly (when treating the histories of ancient Rome and Western Europe)
that individual freedom and state despotism are not mutually exclusive. Walicki
observes that, for Kireevskii, ‘notions of individual liberty were only an
apparent contradiction of the principle of external authority’, because for him
both were rooted in ‘the individual’s separation from the collective
consciousness, in the licence granted to him to make an arbitrary
interpretation of revealed truths living on in the collective consciousness of
the people’.[xiv]
The conservative romantics’ preoccupation with this ‘apparent contradiction’
seems important, because it reflects what Chamberlain called ‘Russian
philosophy’s chief problem: how to reconcile individuality with selflessness’.[xv]
Kireevskii seems to be hinting that the conundrum, or the seeming lack of
reconciliation, can become resolved through a return to participation in a
communal spiritual life – as if by replacing attention to selflessness qua submission to the authority of a
repressive state, with attention to selflessness qua submission to the spiritual truths of collective religiosity.
2.8.19
[i] Adam
Zagajewski, A Defense of Ardor,
trans. by Clare Cavanagh (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2005; first
publ. 2004), p. 172; The Slavophile
Controversy: History of a Conservative Utopia in Nineteenth-Century Russian
Thought, trans. by Hilda Andrews-Rusiecka (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975),
p. 237.
[ii]
Walicki, pp. 454, 460, 279.
[iii]
Walicki, p. 504.
[iv]
Lesley Chamberlain, Motherland: A
Philosophical History of Russia (New York: Rookery Press, 2007; first publ.
[London(?)]: [n. pub.], 2004), pp. 165, 166.
[v]
Walicki, p. 355.
[vi] Ibid.
[vii]
Walicki, p. 168.
[viii]
Walicki, pp. 223, 72, 161, 334-35.
[ix]
Walicki, pp. 148, 151, 326.
[x]
Walicki, p. 150.
[xi]
Walicki, pp. 152, 154, 155 (quoting Schlegel), 307.
[xii]
Kireevskii quoted from Walicki, pp. 151-52, 151.
[xiii]
Walicki, pp. 157, 307, 157-58, 317.
[xiv]
Walicki, pp. 173, 139.
[xv]
Chamberlain, p. 57.
Comments
Post a Comment