Ivan Kireevskii's Christian Rationality
In the view of
one respected historian of Russian philosophy, Ivan Kireevskii’s was ‘the most
powerful philosophic mind of the first half of the nineteenth century’ in
Russia. Yet Kireevskii (1806-56) was not powerfully productive; so that, as the
same historian notes, Kireevskii ‘wrote a series of sketches, but did not carry
his projected works to conclusion’.[i] What
Abbott Gleason – in his 1972 biographical study of the philosopher – termed
Kireevskii’s ‘inertia’, or his ‘physical weakness and spiritual passivity’,
points to characteristics of what has traditionally been called a ‘feminine’
personality. Gleason attaches to Kireevskii labels such as ‘fragile’, ‘sensitive’,
and ‘prone to passivity and withdrawal’.[ii] Yet,
importantly, such actionless inwardness also reflected the ambience of the
intellectual milieu he inhabited in Russia in the early decades of the
nineteenth-century.
Gleason stresses
that Kireevskii was not always a Slavophile, and that he originally ‘admitted,
at least by implication, that everything in Russia began with the great
Tsar-Jacobin, Peter the Great’. Kireevskii could not begin by critiquing the
rationalization of Russian society, because to start with he was ‘a
Europeanized intellectual, who fully realized how much of Russia’s culture
resulted from Peter’s rupture with the past’. This meant that – and rather than
offering a political critique of bureaucratic absolutism – Kireevskii and his
friends in the ‘Lovers of Wisdom’ (Liubomudry) circle in the 1820s
involved themselves with the study of Hegelian philosophy, with German
rationality, as a feature of their tendency towards apolitical inwardness.
Gleason writes of ‘the passion, greater even than that of their German cousins,
with which the Russians substituted philosophy for politics and other pursuits
and satisfactions of the real world’. He quotes Alexandre Koyré’s estimation
that ‘nothing is more characteristic of the mentality of the generation of the
twenties […] than this “apoliticism”’.[iii]
The political
reality of Nicholas I’s regime impacted on Kireevskii in 1832, with the
suppression of the journal the European – of which Kireevskii had been
the editor – after just one issue. Gleason writes that ‘it is clear that the European
marks the high-water mark of those elements in Kireevskii’s personality and
intellectual makeup which […] tended to accept the modern world and Russian
society as they were’. Now ‘the bureaucratic absolutism of Nicholas had […]
crushed the most important enterprise of his life and dimmed his hopes for a
gradual rapprochement between Russia and Europe’. I would suggest that it was
precisely this personal experience of the workings of the autocratic
rationality of state bureaucracy, which stimulated Kireevskii’s search for a
more elevated or open form of reason. Gleason emphasizes that the closure of
the European was ‘a crucial step in the formation of his Slavophile
views’, and in the formation of ‘a whole new attitude toward religion, toward Orthodoxy,
which became the basis for his new view of Russian culture’.[iv] Discussing
the influence on Kireevskii at this stage of Aleksei Khomiakov’s views, Gleason
notes how the latter’s Slavophilism was ‘inimical’ to ‘rationalism in general,
whether political or intellectual, whether bourgeois or bureaucratic’. Moreover,
the heightened inwardness of Kireevskii’s section of the intelligentsia in the
1820s was continuing into the 1830s, a decade (in Gleason’s words) ‘of
repression – […] of mysticism, of withdrawal and passivity’. Thus Kireevskii’s
Slavophilism was constituted by a sort of Schelling-tinged meta-rationalism. Kireevskii
saw that (the later) Schelling had ‘overcome Hegelian “rationalism” by turning
to the subliminal “feelings” and pre-cognitive experiences which underlie
rational thought’: now Schelling’s critique was to be developed further using
ideas garnered from the patristic Christianity to which Kireevskii was turning.[v]
It is important
to stress the political radicalism enabled by the Slavophiles’ attitude towards
prevailing rationality. As Gleason points out, ‘their view of the relations
which ought to obtain between state and society, their essential hostility to
an activist, rationalizing, modern state, was nearly as repugnant to the
Russian government as the eclectic radicalism of the Westerners.’ The
government understood that ‘for all their “Russianness”, for all their religiosity
and hostility to “Western” liberalism’, the Slavophiles were ‘really an
oppositional force’. Kireevskii was now hostile to Peter the Great because
Kireevskii identified the Romanov dynasty with political rationalism. Whilst in
England and France rationalism had been ‘primarily the weapon of the ascendant
bourgeoisie’, as Gleason notes, ‘in Russia, as in much of the rest of Europe’,
rationalism had been ‘primarily […] an instrument of the centralizing
monarchy’. Of course the Russian gentry itself ‘originated […] as the creature
of the state’, being a product of Peter’s Table of Ranks, and so it was
unsurprising that the gentry in general ‘did not perceive the threat of “Western
rationalism”’. Only a marginal conservative intellectual such as Kireevskii
could focus on rationalization as a key process underpinning the workings of
the modern state. Hence Kireevskii became – as Gleason puts it – ‘more keenly
aware than any Russian of his day of the great problems which the industrial
revolution and the growth of the bureaucratic state were in the process of
presenting’, and in this way anticipated the sociological approaches to modern
dehumanization produced by later thinkers such as Ferdinand Tönnies, Max Weber
and Theodor Adorno. For now, however, I want to focus back on the specifically
Slavophile insights of Kireevskii’s that early-mid nineteenth-century Russia
had (in Gleason’s words) ‘nearly lost its religiously based, communal social
order’, and that ‘the political institutions which corresponded to it had been
thoroughly perverted by the ruling dynasty’.[vi]
Kireevskii’s Slavophilism represents a Russian form of the
Europe-wide intellectual reaction to the French Revolution. ‘The belief that
the ills of the modern world were largely brought on by rationalism,
secularism, and the flouting of tradition was central to the expressed views of
most of the important theoreticians of romantic conservatism in Europe.’ In the
face of the bourgeoisie’s ‘intellectual and political rationalism’ as well as
‘the “enlightened,” rationalizing despots’, Gleason adds, thinkers such as
Franz Baader, Adam Műller and Friedrich Schlegel had opposed ‘the irrational,
the historically sanctioned, the communal, the aristocratic’. Gleason focussed
on how the intellectual historian Andrzej Walicki sees Kireevskii’s
‘integralism’ to be ‘part and parcel of a sweeping critique of revolutionary
rationalism’ (Gleason). Indeed, ‘both Walicki and [Eberhard] Műller have
stressed the similarities between Kireevskii’s “integralism” […] and that of
Friedrich Schegel’.[vii]
In his The Slavophile Controversy (1975), Walicki quotes Schlegel’s
statements from his Philosophy of Life (1828) that philosophy’s main
task is to reconstruct man’s ‘primary unity’ with the help of religious faith, and
to separate the human soul from the ‘autocratic rule of reason’. The
similarities between Schlegel’s and Kireevskii’s modes of ‘anti-rationalistic
“integralism”’, Walicki maintains, derive from ‘the common desire of both
philosophers to combat the “social atomization” of bourgeois liberal society
from a conservative vantage-point’.[viii]
In another post I have already quoted Walicki on Kireevskii’s foregrounding of the opposition of ‘rationalism and pure Christianity’. Gleason too finds that ‘any analysis of Slavophilism must place […] the opposition between the abstract rationalism of the West and the integral Christian civilization of pre-Petrine Russia at the heart of the matter’. Resisting Khomiakov’s view that ‘the demise of patriarchal Russia’ was due to the historical ‘consolidation of the idea of the state’, Kireevskii – as Gleason observes – instead blamed specifically the Church Council of 1551 which, Kireevskii thought, introduced rationalism into the Orthodox Church and hence paved the way for religious formalism, the Schism and then Peter the Great’s revolutions. Gleason points out that the Council of 1551 is in fact often regarded as representing a key stage in the state’s domination over the Church anyway, and maintains that Kireevskii is ‘very vague as to precisely what the baneful effects of the Council were’. It is clear, however, how Kireevskii understood Western Christianity to have been infiltrated by Roman, formalist rationalism; he saw how Aristotelian logic underpinned scholasticism.[ix]
As Gleason summarizes,
‘Kireevskii’s respect for the traditional, the historical, and the “empirical”
was brought to bear against the Roman spirit of Roman Catholicism – and
Protestantism, its dialectical companion.’ Kireevskii’s fascination with ‘the
problem of breaking through the constructions of the mind to reality itself’,
or with ontological issues, of course lay behind this respect for the
empirical.[x]
His concern with ontology connects to his criticism of Hegel’s rationalism, or
what his 1856 landmark article ‘On the Necessity and Possibility of New
Principles in Philosophy’ called ‘one intellectual view based on the identity
of reason and being’. Kireevskii thought that such a rationalism inhibited
access to reality; he agreed with what Gleason describes as ‘the starting point
for Schelling’s later philosophy’, his ‘growing conviction that “reality” could
not be grasped by the purely intellectual – or “rational” – processes of
traditional metaphysics’.[xi] For
such idealist metaphysics proposes, in its ultimate Hegelian variant, that – as
Kireevskii memorably writes – ‘the world’s whole being is a shadowy dialectic
of my own reason, and reason is the self-consciousness of universal being’. But
only ‘through the internal development of the understanding [within the]
integral personality can we understand substantiality’. Kireevskii argues that
we gain cognition of reality not by rationality alone, but instead with our
whole being. ‘The chief condition for the preservation of cognitive intimacy
with being is the connection of man’s cognitive processes to his whole
spiritual sphere – i.e. wholeness of spirit.’ (V. Zenkovsky)[xii]
As Gleason puts
it, ‘Schelling’s attack on Hegel remained, for Kireevskii, the great attack on
the stronghold of Western rationalism.’ The danger in stressing this fact – in
stressing Kireevskii’s affinities with Schelling’s critique of Hegelian
rationalism from a Christian perspective – however of course remains apparent:
that we lock ourselves within a binary opposition of rationality to
Christianity. In this situation it can be helpful to think about the diverging methodological
approaches to Kireevskii’s writings taken by Walicki and Eberhard Műller, as
noted by Gleason. Whilst Műller underlined Kireevskii’s relation to ‘the moment
in the intellectual history of Europe when Hegelian “rationalism” ceased to
satisfy the most searching and thoughtful men of the age’, Walicki – Gleason
continues – instead ‘tends to see Kireevskii in terms of the “classic” European
conservatism – largely German – which was so brilliantly anatomized by Karl
Mannheim’. Gleason’s own brilliant strategy is to fuse Walicki and Műller’s
perspectives, by venturing that ‘one can say that Schelling’s attack on what he
considered to be Hegel’s rationalism is a further development of Adam Műller’s
and Friedrich Schlegel’s criticism of the political and social theory of the
Enlightenment’. Gleason thus sociologizes Schelling and Kireevskii’s shared project
of ontological meta-rationalism, or at any rate places the project within
social history as much as within intellectual history. ‘Schelling’s – and
Kireevskii’s – search for a kind of Christian empiricism belongs to a specific
moment in the history of European society, as well as to a specific moment in
the history of European philosophy.’[xiii]
Interestingly, when grounding Schelling and Kireevskii’s goal in wider
historical currents in this way, Gleason invents a category – ‘Christian
empiricism’ – which in itself subverts the binary opposition of rationality to
Christianity.
A closer
examination of ‘On the Necessity and Possibility of New Principles in
Philosophy’ reveals Kireevskii himself moving beyond a constricting opposition
of rationality to Christianity – and in so doing justifying Zenkovsky’s
assessment that, ‘even more than Chaadaev or Khomiakov’, Kireevskii ‘may be
called a “Christian philosopher”’. Though Kireevskii was ‘a genuine philosopher
who never at any point repressed the functioning of reason’, Zenkovsky
maintained, Kireevskii’s ‘idea of reason as an organ of cognition was wholly
defined in terms of the deepened conception of reason which had found
expression in Christianity’. In his article he indeed saw religion
strengthening rationality, noting ‘the main difference in Orthodox thinking’ to
be that ‘it seeks not to arrange separate concepts according to the demands of
faith, but rather to elevate reason itself above its usual level’. Conversely,
Kireevskii argued that rationality bolsters Christianity:
‘Schelling did
not deliberately turn to Christianity but came to it naturally through the profound
and correct development of his rational self-consciousness. For the possibility
of the consciousness of man’s basic relationship to God lies in the very core
of human reason, and in its very nature.’
The view that
rationality bolsters Christianity rests on a recognition of the limitations of
rationality – on a humility stemming from an awareness of weakness. Kireevskii
points out that if rational thought ‘saw itself as one of the instruments for
the cognition of truth, and not as the only one, it would present its
deductions as provisional and referent solely to its limited point of view’. Kireevskii
valued acceptance of his own powerlessness as a philosopher. ‘If, however, philosophical
reason realized its limitations, it would, through its development within these
limitations, adopt another orientation capable of leading it to fuller
knowledge.’[xiv]
23.1.20
[i] V. V. Zenkovsky, A
History of Russian Philosophy, trans. by George L. Kline, 2 vols (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1967; first publ. 1953), I, p. 13.
[ii] Abbott Gleason, European
and Muscovite: Ivan Kireevsky and the Origins of Slavophilism (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1972), pp. 91, 43, 287.
[iii] Gleason, pp. 68, 69,
33; Koyré quoted from p. 39.
[iv] Gleason, pp. 94, 150,
151, 95, 96.
[v] Gleason, pp. 151, 95; Russian
Philosophy: Volume I, ed. by James M. Edie and others, 3 vols (Knoxville:
University of Tennessee Press, 1994; first publ. Quadrangle Books, 1965), pp.
167-68.
[vi] Gleason, pp. 5, 170,
169-70, 288, 291, 4-5.
[vii] Gleason, pp. 1, 169,
285.
[viii]
The Slavophile Controversy: History of a Conservative
Utopia in Nineteenth-Century Russian Thought, trans. by Hilda Andrews-Rusiecka
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), pp. 155 (quoting Schlegel), 154, 155.
[ix] Walicki, p. 168;
Gleason, pp. 184, 168, 325 n. 31, 251.
[x] Gleason, pp. 242, 271.
[xi] ‘On the Necessity and
Possibility of New Principles in Philosophy’, in ed. by James M. Edie and
others, pp. 171-213 (p. 181); Gleason, p. 118.
[xii] Kireevskii quoted from
Zenkovsky, pp. 219, 220; Zenkovsky, p. 219.
[xiii] Gleason, pp. 329 n. 8,
291-92.
[xiv] Zenkovsky, p. 212; ed.
by James M. Edie and others, pp. 198, 211, 207.
Comments
Post a Comment